Analysis, Language, and Concepts: The Second Paradox of Analysis
Author(s): Felicia Ackerman
Source: Philosophical Perspectives , 1990, Vol. 4, Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind (1990), pp. 535-543
Published by: Ridgeview Publishing Company
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/2214203
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms
and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Perspectives
This content downloaded from 128.195.203.196 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 18:07:22 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philosophical Perspectives, 4
Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind, 1990
ANALYSIS, LANGUAGE, AND CONCEPTS: THE SECOND PARADOX OF ANALYSIS’
Felicia Ackerman Brown University
Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences
In an earlier paper (Ackerman, forthcoming; see also Ackerman 1981 and 1986), I distinguished two paradoxes of analysis and offered a solution to one. This paper offers a solution to the other and also touches on some general issues about analysis, language, and concepts.
The two paradoxes of analysis can be illustrated and distinguished by considering the following propositions.
(1) To be an instance of knowledge is to be an instance of
justified true belief not essentially grounded in any falsehood.
(2) To be an instance of knowledge is to be an instance of knowledge.
(3) A correct analysis is given by saying that to be a brother is to be a male sibling.
(4) A correct analysis is given by saying that to be a brother is to be a brother.
The first paradox arises from the relation between (1) and (2). (1), if true, illustrates an important type of philosophical analysis. For purposes of illustration, I will assume (1) is a correct analysis. To suppose that (1) gives a correct analysis, however, leads to the following notorious problem. If the concept of justified true belief not essentially grounded in any falsehood is the analysans of the
concept of knowledge, it would seem that they are the same concept and hence that (2) would have to be the same proposition as (1). But
This content downloaded from 128.195.203.196 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 18:07:22 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
536 / Felicia Ackerman
propositions (1) and (2) seem clearly diverse; for example, (2) is trivial
(in the sense that understanding it entails believing it), while (1) can
be informative and in fact was only recently arrived at by philosophers.
This is the paradox philosophers generally call “the” paradox of
analysis. But there is another paradox of analysis that can be gleaned
by reading classic writings on analysis, such as Moore, 1952 and Langford, 1952. This second paradox of analysis arises from the relation between (3) and (4). If (3) is true, it would seem that the
concept of being a brother would have to be the same concept as
the concept of being a male sibling and that (4) would also have to
be true and in fact would have to be the same proposition as (3).
Yet (3) is true and (4) is false.
Both these paradoxes rest upon the assumptions that analysis is
a relation wholly between concepts rather than one between entities
of other. sorts, such as linguistic expressions, and that in a correct
analysis, analysans and analysandum will be the same concept. Both these assumptions are explicit in Moore, 1952. But some of Moore’s remarks hint at a solution to the second paradox-that a statement
of an analysis is a statement partly about the concept involved and partly about the verbal expressions used to express it. (Moore, 1952, p. 283.) He says he thinks a solution of this sort is bound to be right,
but fails to suggest one because he cannot see just how the analysis can be even partly about the expressions.
In this paper I will suggest a way and thus offer a solution to the
second paradox. It is important to see that this sort of approach cannot possibly provide a solution to the first, however. The two
paradoxes must be clearly distinguished. This can be done by means of the Frege-inspired sense-individuation condition, which is the condition that two expressions have the same sense if and only if they can be interchanged salva veritate whenever used in propositional attitude contexts. If the expressions for the analysans
and the analysandum in (1) met this condition, (1) and (2) would not raise the first paradox, but the second paradox arises regardless of
whether the expressions for the analysans and the analysandum meet
this condition. The second paradox is a matter of the failure of such expressions to be interchangeable salva veritate in sentences involving such contexts as ‘A correct analysis is given by’. Thus, a solution aimed only at such contexts can solve the second paradox. This is clearly false for the first paradox, however, which will apply
This content downloaded from 128.195.203.196 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 18:07:22 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Second Paradox of Analysis / 537
to all pairs of propositions expressed by sentences in which
expressions for pairs of analysanda and analysantia raising the first paradox are interchanged. It seems obviously unacceptable to hold that the proposition that John knows that the moon is not made of green cheese is partly about language because it can be believed
without believing the proposition that John has justified true belief
not essentially grounded in any falsehood that the moon is not made of green cheese.
My solution to the first paradox (Ackerman, 1981, 1986, and
forthcoming) rested on denying Moore’s view that analysans and analysandum have to be the same concept in a correct analysis.
Instead, I argued that in analyses raising the first paradox, the analysans and analysandum are diverse concepts that are necessarily and a priori knowable to be coextensive and are further related in
a special epistemic way I spelled out. Such a solution seems attractive
in cases such as (1) and (2), for the concepts of knowledge and justified true belief not essentially grounded in any falsehood seem on the face of it to be quite different. The first is readily grasped, the second fairly difficult; the first is employed in the thoughts of many people,
the second in those of relatively few, perhaps only professional philosophers and their students. But this sort of solution seems precluded where we have pairs of synonymous expressions that are
interchangeable salva veritate whenever used in propositional attitude contexts, and thus where analysis raises only the second paradox and.not the first at all. Purely for the sake of illustration, I will assume throughout this paper that ‘brother’ and ‘male sibling’ are such a pair of expressions, and that the concept of being a brother is identical with the concept of being a male sibling. (Nothing in my argument hinges on this particular example, and readers who dislike
the example can substitute one of their own.) This makes it reasonable
to suppose, with Moore (1952), that (3) is partly about words, while rejecting the view that it is wholly about the verbal expressions ‘brother’ and ‘male sibling’ and not about the concept at all-a view Moore opposes by arguing as follows.
For what are you doing [in saying simply that the
expressions ‘brother’ and ‘male sibling’ have the same
meaning]? You are merely asserting, with regard to two verbal expressions, that…the meaning they have is the same. You are not mentioning the meaning of either, or saying
This content downloaded from 128.195.203.196 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 18:07:22 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
538 / Felicia Ackerman
what the meaning of either is; but are merely making a
statement, which could be completely understood by a
person who had not the least idea what either expression meant. A man might point out to me two expressions in a
language of which I was completely ignorant and tell me
that they had the same meaning, without telling me what
they meant. So far as he was merely telling me that they
had the same meaning, I should completely understand what he told me-namely that those two expressions had the
same meaning…. But if this were all he was doing, he would
not have told me anything at all about any concept or idea,
which either of the expressions expressed and would
therefore certainly not have been giving me an analysis of any concept….(Moore, 1952, pp. 280-1, italics in original.)
But he goes on to say
An obvious suggestion to make is that, if you [assert (3)], you are making a statement both about the concept brother and also about the two verbal expressions used, which
would explain why this statement is not the same statement
as [(4)]. But this suggestion would be compatible with its
being the case that [(3)] is merely a conjunction of the assertion “The verbal expression ‘x is a brother’ has the same meaning as the expression ‘x is a male sibling”‘ with some other assertion which is merely an assertion about the
concept “x is a brother” and not an assertion about any verbal expression. But I do not think this can possibly be the case: what would the second assertion in this supposed
conjunction be? (Moore, 1952, p. 283, italics in original.)
An obvious reply to Moore’s final question here would be to say
the second conjunct is simply that the concept of being a brother
is identical with the concept of being a male sibling. Then (3) would
be explicated as
(5) A correct analysis is given by saying that the verbal
expression ‘x is a brother’ has the same meaning as the verbal expression ‘x is a male sibling’ and the concept of
being a brother is identical with the concept of being a male sibling.
This content downloaded from 128.195.203.196 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 18:07:22 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Second Paradox of Analysis / 539
But then the original problem rearises, as the identity of the concept
of being a brother and the concept of being a male sibling means
(5) is the same proposition as
(6) A correct analysis is given by saying that the verbal
expression ‘x is a brother’ has the same meaning as the
verbal expression ‘x is a male sibling’ and the concept of
being a brother is identical with the concept of being a
brother.
But (6), like (4), seems clearly false.
The inadequacy of (5) should not make us reject the general view that (3) is partly about words and partly about concepts. Moore is
obviously right in his above quoted remark that the general position
that (3) is partly about words and partly about concepts is compatible with its being the case that (3) is “merely a conjunction of the assertion
‘The verbal expression ‘x is a brother’ has the same meaning as the
expression ‘x is a male sibling” with some other assertion which is
merely about the concept “x is a brother” and not an assertion about any verbal expression.” (Moore, 1952, p. 283, italics in original.) But it obviously does not follow that every particular proposal that makes (3) partly about words and partly about concepts is compatible with
saying (3) is merely a conjunction of this sort and hence open to the
sort of objection facing (5). Here is such a proposal that is not.
(7) A correct analysis is given by saying that the verbal expression ‘x is a brother’ expresses the same concept as is expressed by the conjunction of the verbal expressions ‘x is male’ when used to express the concept of being male and
‘x is a sibling’ when used to express the concept of being a
sibling.
(7) pairs each constituent concept in the analysans separately with the verbal expression that expresses it, so (7) cannot be paraphrased
as a conjunction that leads to the problems of (5). I suggest (7) as the solution to Moore’s question of how analysis can be partly about words and partly about concepts and thus as an account of (3) that does not entail anything raising the problems of (4) and (5) and so solves the second paradox of analysis. The rest of this paper will discuss implications of this solution and possible objections to it.
An important point about (7) is as follows. Stripped of its philosophical jargon (‘analysis’, ‘concept’, ‘x is a …’), (7) seems to state
This content downloaded from 128.195.203.196 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 18:07:22 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
540 / Felicia Ackerman
the sort of information generally stated in a definition of the verbal
expression ‘brother’ in terms of the verbal expressions ‘male’ and
‘sibling’, where this definition is designed to draw upon the listeners’ antecedent understanding of the verbal expressions ‘male’ and
‘sibling’ and thus to tell listeners what the verbal expression ‘brother’
really means, instead of merely providing the information that two
verbal expressions are synonymous without specifying the meaning
of either one. Thus, the solution to the second paradox seems to make the sort of analysis that gives rise to this paradox a matter of
specifying the meaning of a verbal expression in terms of separate
verbal expressions already understood and sayi
Delivering a high-quality product at a reasonable price is not enough anymore.
That’s why we have developed 5 beneficial guarantees that will make your experience with our service enjoyable, easy, and safe.
You have to be 100% sure of the quality of your product to give a money-back guarantee. This describes us perfectly. Make sure that this guarantee is totally transparent.
Read moreEach paper is composed from scratch, according to your instructions. It is then checked by our plagiarism-detection software. There is no gap where plagiarism could squeeze in.
Read moreThanks to our free revisions, there is no way for you to be unsatisfied. We will work on your paper until you are completely happy with the result.
Read moreYour email is safe, as we store it according to international data protection rules. Your bank details are secure, as we use only reliable payment systems.
Read moreBy sending us your money, you buy the service we provide. Check out our terms and conditions if you prefer business talks to be laid out in official language.
Read more